PHIL 222 – Philosophy of Law                   Spring 2014

Syllabus – keep handy for reference

 

Dr. Aeon J. Skoble

341 Tillinghast, x2460

Email: askoble@bridgew.edu     Web: http://webhost.bridgew.edu/askoble

Office hours: M 10-11, TR 1:45-2:45, or by appointment

 

Texts:

“Philosophy of Law” course pack available at BSU bookstore.

There will be additional readings either posted on the course web page or distributed in class.  All readings mentioned are required unless otherwise noted.  I will also assign some films to be viewed at home – these may be the subject of writing prompts and hence required.

 

Overview and objectives:

This course is an exploration of a variety of philosophical issues pertaining to law.  We will not be “studying the law” in the sense of learning what all the laws are, although we will refer to real laws and court decisions in the course of our investigations.  Philosophy of Law, like the  “philosophy of” other things, is concerned with the theoretical underpinnings of our subject; ontological, epistemological, and ethical ramifications or presuppositions of our subject; questions of justification.  More specifically, we will examine questions such as: What is law?  Where does it come from?  What is the nature of legal and judicial reasoning?  What grounds  legal authority? How are rights understood in the law?  How shall we understand the relation between morality and law?  What is the grounding of a system of punishment?  What is responsibility in the law?  Our objectives for this semester are to look at some of the main philosophical theories pertaining to these questions, get a better sense of what law is and what legal systems are, and to learn to think philosophically about these issues.  Although this class is beneficial to the pre-law student, its essence is philosophy.

 

Requirements:

First of all, please note that you are required to do all assigned readings and viewings, whether from the texts, on handouts, or on the internet, and to be prepared to comment on them if called on in class to do so.  Repeated unpreparedness indicates that you are not taking the class seriously and will result in grade reduction as appropriate. Also, regular attendance is a requirement of the class.  This is a reflection of the fact that the primary vehicle for learning the material is the class itself, of which you should see yourself as a part.  You should regard coming to class as the norm. Obviously there is such a thing as a good reason to miss class, but be sure you limit your absences to such occasions, as absences in excess of three will result in reduction of overall grade no matter what your average is.  Excessive lateness will count as one or more absences -- besides being disruptive, you are missing something.  If you do have to miss class, it is your responsibility to get the notes, and any announcements or additional assignments, from a classmate.   (On the other hand, if I am late, it almost certainly means I am ill – call the department office at x1258.)  In general, try to observe some of the ground rules of civilized society: Anything with an off switch should be off (as should, ideally, hats), eat and drink quietly and discreetly, don’t read the newspaper or do homework for another class, don’t go to sleep.  You are not to use your phone during class.  Disruptive behavior will result in your being asked to leave.  Conversely, constructive participation will be rewarded.  Philosophy has, as its essence, the idea of conversation.  There will be some lecturing as I introduce you to material, but you should feel free to ask questions -- of me, and of your classmates -- and to agree or disagree as you see fit.  However, you must strive to maintain an atmosphere of civil discourse.  There is a difference between philosophical argument (which is cooperative and constructive) and belligerent bickering. 

Subject to adjustments as noted above, your grade will primarily be calculated thus:

Weekly response: each week, with one or two exceptions, I will ask you to respond to some question or reflect on some problem.  You will reply via email not later than Sunday at noon.  Your reply need not be more than a paragraph, but must demonstrate critical reflection and real engagement with the material.  Successful completion of all weekly responses=40%

Two short papers (approx. 3 pages) I will ask you to (and help you figure out how to) expand two of your weekly responses into full essays.  This can happen at any time, but you will not be asked to do them both in consecutive weeks.  @30% each=60%

Late papers will be penalized one letter grade per day.  Papers should be written in WORD, and  be configured to 12-point Times New Roman, double-spaced with 1-inch margins all around.  Your name, date, and “PHIL222” should appear top right on the first page.  Page numbering on.  Documentation of sources on a separate page following the end of your paper. The papers should be a .doc or .docx file sent as an attachment to an email.  The weekly responses should just be in the body of an email, and in both cases, this should be an email sent from your bridgew.edu account, with a subject line saying “weekly response #x” or “first essay” etc.

 

Outline:

The course is divided into several distinct but often related topics.  Part 1 is on the nature of law. What is law?  What makes a valid law valid?   What is the “natural” in “natural law”?  Where does law come from?  Part 2 is concerned with theories of interpretation, some of which you may have heard discussed: formalism, originalism, realism, and so on.  Part 3 will be an exploration of the evolution of law and legal systems, including a look at the idea of polycentric law.  Part 4 is devoted to several philosophical problems in the law: the nature of punishment, the concept of responsibility, rights theory, and civil disobedience theory.  If time permits we will discuss all four of these.  The basic outline, mapped onto a calendar, will be as follows: 

Week of:         Topic, reading assignment for that week; other notes:

Jan 23              Distribution of syllabus; intro to course

Jan 28              Begin Part 1  (No class Jan 30)

Feb 4               (No class Feb 6)

Feb 11-13       

Feb 18-20       

Feb 25             Begin Part 2 (No class Feb 27)

Mar 4-6          

Mar 18-20      

Mar 25-27       Begin Part 3

Apr 1-3           

Apr 8-10           

Apr 15-17        Begin Part 4

Apr 22-24       

Apr 29- May 1

The above calendar is subject to change and deliberately vague to allow us some flexibility.  As the discussions proceed, we may find some topics expanded, others reduced.  See below for a  detailed outline.

 

*Zero Tolerance Policy on cheating and plagiarism.  That’s an F for the course.

 

Course Outline with readings:

Selections with an asterisk are not in the course pack as they are available online.  I will provide the URLs for these selections.  Other selections may be handed out or posted.

 

Jan 28-Feb 20:  The nature of law

1.      H.L.A Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford UP, 1961) , pp. 77-96

2.      *Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, questions 90-97

3.      Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law (Yale UP 1964), pp. 33-38

4.      *Frederic Bastiat, The Law (FEE, 1987 (1850))

5.      Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (U of Chicago Press, 1960), pp. 148-175

6.      Friedrich Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty (U of Chicago Press, 1973), pp. 35-54, 72-144

Feb 25-Mar 20: Legal interpretation

1.      Handout

2.      Richard Posner, “Legal Formalism, Legal Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes and the Constitution,” Case Western Reserve University Law Review, v. 37 (1987), pp 179ff

3.      John Hasnas, “The Myth of the Rule of Law,” Wisconsin Law Review, vol 1995 no. 1, pp. 199ff

Mar 25-Apr 10: Polycentrism and the evolution of law

1.      Bruce Benson, “Are Public Goods Really Common Pools? Considerations of the Evolution of Policing and Highways in England,” Economic Inquiry XXXII (April 1994), pp. 249-271

2.      Joseph R. Peden, “Property Rights in Celtic Irish Law,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 1 (1977), pp. 81-95

3.      David Friedman, “Private Creation and Enforcement of Law – A Historical Case,” Journal of Legal Studies 8 (1979), pp. 399-415

4.      Paul Milgrom, Douglass North, and Barry Weingast, “The Role of Institutions in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private Judges, and the Champagne Fairs,” Economics and Politics 2 (1990), pp. 1-23

5.      Bruce Benson, Legal Evolution in Primitive Societies, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 144, 5 (1988), pp. 772-788

6.      Terry L. Anderson and P.J. Hill, “An American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not So Wild, Wild West,” Journal of Libertarian Studies  3, 1 (1979), pp. 9-29.

7.      Harold Berman, Law and Revolution (Harvard UP, 1983), pp. 520-558

8.      *Randy Barnett, “Pursuing Justice in a Free Society,” Part One (Criminal Justice Ethics Summer-Fall 1985); Part Two (Criminal Justice Ethics Winter-Spring 1986)

 

 

 

Apr 15-May 1: philosophical issues in the law

1.      *Jeremy Bentham, The Principles of Morals and Legislation (Prometheus Books 1988), pp. 170-188

2.      *Immanuel Kant, “On the Right to Punish,” The Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge UP, 1991), pp. 140-144

3.      John Rawls, “Two Concepts of Rules,” Philosophical Review 64 (1955), pp. 3-13

4.      Herbert Morris, “Persons and Punishment,” The Monist (1968)

5.      Plato, “Crito,” in Five Dialogues, ed. G.M.A. Grube (Hackett 1981), pp. 45-56

6.      *Thoreau, “Civil Disobedience”

7.      John Rawls, “Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play,” in S. Hook, ed., Law and Philosophy (NYU Press 1964), pp. 3-18

8.      A. John Simmons, “The Principle of Fair Play,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol 8, no 4 (1979), pp. 307-337

9.      Richard Epstein, “A Theory of Strict Liability,” Journal of Legal Studies vol 2 (Jan 1973)

10.  Hart and Honore, selection TBD

11.  *Thomas Jefferson, Declaration of Independence

12.  Rights theory handout

 

Films assigned for home viewing may include: 12 Angry Men, Breaker Morant, A Man for All Seasons, Judgement at Nuremberg, The Castle, Billy Budd, Gideon’s Trumpet, Unalienable.

 

Useful online resources:

http://www.supremecourtus.gov/opinions/opinions.html -- The US Supreme Court

http://www.constitution.org/liberlib.htm -- Historical legal writings (includes our Constitution)

http://www.constitution.org/mil/ucmj19970615.htm -- Military law

http://www.law.harvard.edu/library/ -- Harvard Law Library

http://www4.law.cornell.edu/uscode/ -- Searchable US Code

http://www.findlaw.com -- all-purpose resource

http://volokh.com – legal issues blog by UCLA Law Professor Eugene Volokh and others

http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal_theory_lexicon/ -- Lawrence Solum’s Legal Theory Lexicon